Skeptical argument of Descartes :
In this essay, I will examine Rene Descartes' skeptical argument and
responses by
O.K. Bouwsma and Norman Malcolm. I intend to prove that while both
Bouwsma and
Malcolm make points that refute specific parts of Descartes' argument in
their
criticisms, neither is sufficient in itself to refute the whole.
In order to understand Descartes' argument and its sometimes radical
ideas, one
must have at least a general idea of his motives in undertaking the
argument. The
seventeenth century was a time of great scientific progress, and the
blossoming
scientific community was concerned with setting up a consistent standard
to define
what constituted science. Their science was based on conjunction and
empirical
affirmation, ideally without any preconceived notions to taint the
results. Descartes,
however, believed that the senses were unreliable and that science based
solely on
information gained from the senses was uncertain. He was concerned with
finding a
point of certainty on which to base scientific thought. Eventually he
settled on
mathematics as a basis for science, because he believed mathematics and
geometry to
be based on some inherent truths. He believed that it was through
mathematics that we
were able to make sense of our world, and that the ability to think
mathematically was
an innate ability of all human beings. This theory becomes important in
Descartes'
Meditations because he is forced to explain where the mathematical ideas
that he
believed we were born with came from. Having discussed Descartes'
background, I
will now explain the specifics of his argument.
The basis of Descartes' entire argument is that the senses can not
be trusted, and his
objective is to reach a point of certainty, one undeniable truth that
fixes our existence.
He said it best in his own words, "I will . . . apply myself earnestly
and openly to the
general destruction of my former opinions."1 By opinions he meant all
the facts and
notions about the world which he had previously held as truths. Any
point which had
even the slightest hint of doubt was discarded and considered completely
false.
Descartes decided that he would consider all things until he found that
either nothing is
certain, which is itself a point of certainty, or he reached the one
undeniable truth he
was searching for. In order to accomplish this certainty, in the first
Meditation he asks
the reader to assume that they are asleep and that all their sensory
information is the
product of dreams. More significantly, Descartes implies that all
consciousness could
actually be a dream state, thus proving that the senses can be doubted.
The dream
argument has its intrinsic problems, however. One, is that images in
dreams can be
described as "painted images".2 In other words, a dream image is only a
portrait of a
real-life object, place or person. If we are dreaming then it is implied
that at some point
we were conscious and able to perceive these things. If we are able to
perceive these
things then we must admit that we have senses and that our senses are, at
least in part,
true. This was exactly what Descartes was trying to disprove, and it was
one reason he
abandoned the dream argument.
The second problem with this argument is that it points to
mathematics as a point of
certainty. I believe Descartes best explained this in his own words:
"[W]hether I be
awake or asleep, two plus three equals five and a square does not have
more than four
sides: nor does it seem possible that such obvious truths can fall under
the suspicions of
falsity."3 Even when we are dreaming, the laws of mathematics and
geometry hold
true, but they cannot be Descartes' point of certainty for a simple
reason; these
abilities that Descartes believed were innate still had to come from
somewhere. If they
are in our heads when we are born, someone had to put them there.
Descartes'
question is who, and he comes up with two possibilities.
One possibility is that our inherent mathematical abilities are the
gift of a benign
creator, a gift of God. As a supremely good being, he would not allow us
to be
deceived, and mathematical processes would be a point of certain and
undeniable truth.
If this were the case, the idea of mathematics would meet Descartes'
objectives as a
point of certainty. The existence of God, however, can not be proven and
so there is a
second possibility that Descartes proposed. He asks the reader to
imagine that instead
of a benign God, there is an "evil genius . . .who has directed his
entire effort to
misleading [us] "4 In this case, all things in the physical world would
have to be
thought of as deceptions, because all our sensory information, including
ideas of sizes,
shapes and colors would be fed to us by the evil genius. This is enough
to prove that
mathematics cannot be a point of certainty. It is here that he
concludes the first
Meditation.
Having decided that we have no senses that are not deceptive,
Descartes, in the
second Meditation, looks for something outside the world of sensation to
find some
certainty. What he discovers is that he knows he exists. He knows he
exists because
he is thinking he exists. If there is an evil genius out there deceiving
him at least he is
secure in his thoughts. By thinking he exists, by knowing he is
"something", not even
the evil genius can convince him he is "nothing".5 His point of
certainty comes down
to the statement "I am, I exist"6 or more aptly translated "I think,
therefore I am".
Descartes ideas sometimes seem radical or extreme and his argument
has been
challenged many times. Two particular criticisms that we discussed were
Descartes Evil Genius by O.K. Bouwsma and Knowledge Regained by Norman Malcolm.
I would like to examine the significant points each has made in their
criticisms and then
discuss why I believe each argument is damaging but not sufficient to
refute Descartes'
argument.
Bouwsma's criticism focuses on Descartes' idea of an evil genius
creating an illusory
world. His intent was to prove that Descartes' ideas of illusion and
deception were
misleading. First, Bouwsma set out to define "illusions" and to show how
they are
detected. In order to accomplish this goal, he gave the example of the
evil genius turning
the world and everything in it into paper. "An illusion," Bouwsma says,
"is something that
looks like or sounds like, so much like, something else that you either
mistake it for
something else, or you can easily understand how someone might come to do
this."7 In
this first example, the reader watches "Tom" as he is exposed to and
realizes the difference
between the real world and the genius' paper one. Although the evil
genius attempted to
create a realistic world out of paper, Tom saw through the illusion when
he realized the
difference between the paper flowers and real flowers. Tom was not
really deceived by
the paper illusion since he saw through it rather quickly, but he did
experience the
illusion.8 He experienced it and he detected it. Bouwsma, with this
example, is trying to
point out the importance of how people detect illusions. For instance,
Tom detects the
illusion because he knows the difference between flowers and paper. If
he did not know
the difference, he would not be able to detect the illusion and he would
go on being
deceived. Bouwsma also states that it is critical that the genius also
understand the
difference between his illusion and reality even if Tom does not.
Bouwsma then admits that Descartes had something slightly different
in mind. He asks
the reader what would happen if Descartes' ideas were true, if the
genius' illusion were so
perfect that it would be impossible to tell the difference between the
illusion and reality.
Here Bouwsma sets up a second example, one in which the world has been
destroyed but
Tom goes on believing that the world exists, just as Descartes had
imagined. Tom can not
detect this illusion, for it is completely unlike the paper illusion. In
this example, there is
no difference between the illusory world and the real one. Tom continues
living in what
he thinks is the real world; he goes on being deceived. What Bouwsma
wants the reader
to think about is this idea of deception. Is Tom really being deceived
if he cannot tell the
difference between the real world that the genius destroyed, and the
illusory one the
genius created for him? Bouwsma does not believe that Tom is being
deceived. The evil
genius has a sense of the world that Tom cannot comprehend, because the
genius is the
only one who knows the difference between the real world and the illusion
that he has
created. The word "illusion" then, would mean something different to the
evil genius than
it does to Tom. In order for something to be an illusion, there must be
a way to detect the
reality, like in the paper example. Because there is no way for Tom to
detect the
difference, there is no illusion. For Tom, the illusion becomes the
reality and the
existence of the evil genius does not alter his life.
Malcolm comes up with a very different criticism of Descartes. His
argument focuses
on the simple premise that there is nothing more real to a person than
their sensory
experience. He begins by stating two points commonly associated with
Descartes and
skepticism in order to challenge their validity. First, that any sensory
experience one has
now, can be refuted sometime in the future and second that any statement
made based on
sensory experience is purely hypothetical. Malcolm attempts to show that
the opposite is
true; that sensory experience cannot be refuted and that it is in fact
the only certain
knowledge a person can have.
In order to prove his idea, Malcolm makes three propositions. The
first is what one
would call a factual statement. The second is a type of belief, and the
third is an
observation based on direct sensory experience. Malcolm attempts to show
the reader
that what one considers fact can be proven wrong by new evidence that is
discovered in
the future, but that sensory experience cannot be refuted. For example,
he used the
statement: "The sun is about ninety million miles from the earth."9 New
evidence could
turn up in the future that could drastically alter that figure. This
statement that is
considered fact could be disputed. But what about a statement of near
certain belief, such
as Malcolm's example: "There is a heart in my body."10 This statement
seems impossible
to deny, but what if one were presented with incontrovertible evidence to
the contrary.
Eventually, the person would come to believe the evidence presented to
them and accept
that they had no heart. From this example, one can gather that even
statements of almost
absolute certainty can be proven wrong. Malcolm then examines his final
proposition:
"Here is an ink-bottle."11 This statement is an observation. Malcolm
sees the ink-bottle
on the desk before him. This, Malcolm believes, is a certain,
indisputable statement. If at
that moment he sees the ink-bottle, no evidence can convince him he did
not, at least at
that moment, see the ink-bottle. Direct sensory experience, according to
Malcolm, brings
certainty. As in the example, a person has no direct sensory experience
of the distance of
the sun from the earth. This is the problem with statements of fact and
belief and explains
why they can so easily be proven wrong.
Malcolm believed that people are psychologically impelled to believe
in their immediate
sensory experiences.
Bouwsma and Malcolm offer sound and reasonable arguments, but
neither is able to
completely defeat skepticism. They are damaging to Descartes, but not
destructive to the
whole of skepticism. For example, Bouwsma makes an excellent case
against the evil
genius argument by suggesting that what the genius would consider
illusion, people would
consider reality. But it must be noted that while Bouwsma has made a
valid suggestion, it
does not prove that the evil genius does not exist. It is as impossible
to prove that the evil
genius does not exist as it is to prove that God does exist. Also
Bouwsma's criticism
focused primarily on the evil genius example and did not take into
account the rest of
Descartes' argument. There is a lot more to Descartes' argument than
that particular
point. Descartes only brought up that extreme example in order to prove
that we can not
trust our senses. It is important to keep in mind that Descartes'
purpose in undertaking the
skeptical argument was to find a point of certainty in our existence and
not to prove that
the world is meaningless.
Malcolm has made an admirable case for the validity of the senses,
but upon careful
examination he says very much the same thing as Bouwsma. Namely, that
the senses are
real to us. Bouwsma came to this point by examining the idea of the evil
genius and the
idea of "illusions". Malcolm came to it through examining the
differences between fact,
belief and sensory information. Despite the differences in how they
discovered it, they
both came to the same conclusion. The point is valid and their reasoning
is sound, but it
does not prove that Descartes is wrong.
The strength of the skeptical argument lies in the fact that it can
not be completely
disproved. No one can prove or disprove the existence of an evil genius,
they can only go
so far as to say that it does not matter. This is essentially what
Bouwsma and Malcolm
have done. They tried to prove that the existence of the evil genius
would not make a
difference in our lives. For this reason, I believe that although
Bouwsma and Malcolm
have made a valid point, they have only touched the surface of Descartes'
argument. They
have succeeded in proving that life is not meaningless, but that was not
the purpose of Descartes' argument to begin with.
Skeptical argument of Descartes - Skeptical argument of Descartes - Skeptical argument of Descartes - Skeptical argument of Descartes - Skeptical argument of Descartes - Skeptical argument of Descartes - Skeptical argument of Descartes - Skeptical argument of Descartes - Skeptical argument of Descartes - Skeptical argument of Descartes - Skeptical argument of Descartes - Skeptical argument of Descartes - Skeptical argument of Descartes - Skeptical argument of Descartes
More Essays on Philosophy
Skeptical argument of Descartes :
Essays Index
Skeptical argument of Descartes To HOME PAGE